Interviews – Lisa Herzog, Jason Stanley and others

Philosophy of Markets


Interview by Richard Marshall.

 

Lisa Herzog has worked at the Technical University Munich, Germany, St. Gallen University, Switzerland, and most recently on a research project at the Cluster “Normative Orders” and the Institut für Sozialforschung, Frankfurt, Germany. Her research focuses on the relation between economics and philosophy. Her first book is “Inventing the Market: Smith, Hegel, and Political Theory” (Oxford University Press 2013). In 2014 she published “Freiheit gehört nicht nur den Reichen: Plädoyer für einen zeitgemäßen Liberalismus” [Freedom not just for the rich – a plea for a well-understood liberalism] (C.H.Beck) . Now we’re talking…

 

3:AM:What made you become a philosopher?

Lisa Herzog:I wanted to study philosophy in order to better understand the world, it was a deeply-felt desire that I never questioned. But I was torn about what to combine it with, physics or economics, and I ended up with the latter. And then I simply fell in love with thinking, reading, writing, discussing. I got particularly interested in questions that lie at the intersection of economics and practical philosophy, a field that is still under-explored compared to its real-life importance.

I tried to get away from philosophy a few times, doing internships in other areas such as corporate social responsibility and development cooperation. These were extremely useful experiences, but I also realized that I wanted to continue to do theoretical work, because I came to think that we need better theories in order to change our economic systems, to make them more just and more sustainable.

3:AM:When you discuss the philosophy of markets you begin by pointing out that economists theorizing and modeling markets are inadequate. What’s the problem?

LH:Economic models make simplifying assumptions about human agency and about social interaction. If one only used these models to answer the questions they are supposed to answer, taking into account their methodological limitations, there wouldn’t be any problem. But often they are used to make much wider claims. For example, predications are based on a theoretical model, but with insufficient discussion of whether the assumptions of the model also hold in reality. Along the way, one often finds that normative judgments sneak in, but without being made explicit. Thus, one cannot even ask critical questions, for example whether certain theories serve the interests of certain social groups – whether they are ideologies in the classical sense.

3:AM:You also suggest that philosophers like Rawls’s on justice and others discussing social and political issues like Elizabeth Anderson tend to discuss the market as something to be tamed from the outside rather than be the central subject. Can you say something about this?

LH:Markets are often treated as “black boxes” in normative theorizing, maybe because of an implicit assumption that they are the economists’ business, not ours. Thinking about the boundaries of markets, and about their place in society, is very important, but it is not the only question we can, and should, ask about them. We also need to think about the internal structures of markets: what is their ontology, what kinds of social relations do they create between individuals, what internal distributive features do they have? Some might say that by treating markets from a philosophical perspective, we bestow too much honor to them, replicating the dominance that the economic sphere already has on our lives. But I think we can best resists the tendencies of markets to colonize the life world, as Habermas put it, if we get a better understanding of what they are, and what is problematic about them.

3:AM:So why do you argue that we need a philosophically sophisticated model of the market itself? Was the 2008 north Atlantic crash a wake up call?

LH:The 2008 crash showed that the models that were used to describe the economy were not at all up to the task. It seems crazy in retrospect, but many macroeconomic models did not even include a financial sector! And although behavioral economics – i.e. economic research that takes human psychology seriously – has been pursued for at least 30 years, the mainstream models of markets were all based on assumptions of perfect rationality: all market participant are rationally maximizing their “utility”, without ever making mistakes in how they calculate their options, and without being influenced by effects such as emotions or herding behavior. In addition, the interrelations between the political framework and the internal mechanisms of markets were not considered. And none of these models asked about anything like social justice or the legitimacy of the extraordinary profits that the financial industry made. We need a much broader debate about markets, which takes such dimensions into account.

 

3:AM:You have two giant figures at the centre of your thinking on this matter: Adam Smith and Georg Wilhelm Hegel. For a long time they were considered giants in opposite camps – one the go-to Chicago-style liberal free marketer, the other the go-to ur-Marxist/socialist central planner. You’re building on much recent scholarship that has eroded this position aren’t you?

LH:Yes, if you consider them in their historical context, they are much closer to one another, and Hegel drew explicitly on Smith’s writings. Both have built philosophical systems that include accounts of markets, but also a wider account of human nature, society, politics, history and culture. Of course their emphases and their metaphysical backgrounds are different. But the differences have been exaggerated by the different intellectual traditions that claimed Smith’s and Hegel’s name for them. The reception histories of both are fascinating case studies about how ideas, and even metaphors such as Smith’s “invisible hand”, can take on a life of their own, and be used and abused by different groups, in different historical contexts (I have edited a collection on some of Hegel’s receptions, see here, which illustrates this phenomenon). We inherit these ideas in the form that recent receptions have given them. It is really liberating to go back and read the actual texts, and to see that their thought is much more subtle and interesting than today’s clichés.

3:AM:What do we gain by returning with fresh eyes to Smith and Hegel? What are the debates that you think would be enriched by considering these two giants?

LH:In our societies, markets play an important role – too important a role, many would say. Smith and Hegel describe market societies when the phenomenon was still relatively young, and they explore the various effects markets have on the structures of a society. If we think about social phenomena today, it is easy to overlook the role markets play in them, simply because we got so used to them. In my first book, Inventing the Market, I explore a number of debates in which Smith’s and Hegel’s thought can help us see how markets are interrelated with other questions: our view of the self, our understanding of social justice, of freedom, or of the way in which societies develop in history. I use their accounts as two paradigms of thinking about markets, the contrast of which sheds light on these debates.

3:AM:Regarding commercial society, what similarities do you find between their positions?

LH:Both think of the relation between the state and the market as a tripartite scheme: the state has to secure a framework of fundamental rights, within which the market can take place, but the state then has come back in again, to correct “market failures”, not in the technical sense of the term, but in the broader sense of things that go wrong in markets, or that markets fail to deliver – for example, public education. This way of looking at society is still very widespread: for example, left and right parties often disagree about the relation between levels two and three, the free market and corrective state activities. The modle is helpful in many ways, but one has to keep in mind that it is a model. For example, it diverts attention from the ways in which inequalities in the economic realm can lead to unequal political power, which can lead to distortions not only with regard to corrective state action, but also with regard to the first level, the very way in which the framework of markets is set up.

3:AM:What competing models of this commercial society do Smith and Hegeloffer?

LH:At the risk of oversimplifying, one can say that for Smith, the market solves problems, while for Hegel, it creates problems. Smith draws a very benign picture of the market, as an institution that draws people together, rewards certain virtues, creates more equality in the long run, and makes the society more open and tolerant. For Hegel, markets are an important space for social freedom, but they also lead to inequality and the fragmentation of social life. It is worth remembering that Smith wrote before the Industrial Revolution had really started, whereas Hegel wrote about two generations later, receiving reports from London about the appalling conditions for the working poor. This is one of the reasons why he puts much more emphasis on the role of the state as a unifying force.

3:AM:At one point in your book you put the Smith/Hegel versions of commercial society into play with the Rawls/Sandel debate about the ‘unencumbered self.’ Can you explain what this self is and what the debate is about – and what considering Smith/Hegel adds to it?

LH:Very roughly, the Rawls/Sandel debate was about whether political theorists should start from the notion of a single, autonomous individual, or from the notion of an individual embedded in social structures such as families or religious communities. Smith and Hegel are both very much aware that human beings grow up in communities, and that being part of a community is an important part of human flourishing. They differ in their view of what happens in markets, however: Hegel conceptualized the individual-in-the-market as shaped by the community within which he (it concerned only males, in his day, as the heads of families) worked, with the profession becoming part of his identity. For Smith, in contrast, human beings are embedded in their private lives, but in markets they act as sovereign sellers of their human capital, to use a modern term. What this shows is that we cannot talk about “more” or “less” embeddedness as a one-dimensional relation. There are different ways in which human beings can be embedded or disembedded; even within markets, one can find very different experiences in this respect. It’s striking that the difference between Smith and Hegel corresponds to the character of labor markets in different “varieties of capitalism”: a fluid, flexible model in the “liberal” economies such as the US or the UK, and a more embedded, long-term oriented model in the “coordinated” economies that one finds in Japan and in many European countries.

3:AM:How do they handle the notion of freedom in commercial society?

LH:The cliché is that Smith is a “negative liberty” guy and Hegel a “positive liberty” guy. In fact, both have very nuanced accounts of how different dimensions of freedom are realized in a modern society; the freedom to do what you want with your property – which is sometimes called economic freedom – is only one of them. For example, for Smith the market is also a school of autonomy, because it teaches individuals to become self-reliant and to take their own decisions about their lives; this may seem naive from today’s perspective, but it was written in a time when many people’s lives were predetermined by customs and traditions, and markets indeed had some liberating potential. What I find very interesting is that Smith and Hegel do not try to reduce freedom to one basic notion; rather, they acknowledge its various dimensions, and ask about the ways in which these can find a place in the institutions of a modern society. I find this very convincing as a way of thinking about freedom.

3:AM:There’s a lot of discussion recently about inequality and it’s a key thing in your thinking too. What do Smith and Hegel say about inequality? Is inequality justified? What would they do with the recent material being produced by Thomas Piketty? Would Hegel have remained silent?

LH:What is crucial for Smith and Hegel is whether the members of a society have a status as equal human beings, with equal basic rights and equal dignity, and recognize one another as such. For Smith, the decisive contrast between a commercial society and a feudal society is that in the former, everyone has equal rights, and an equal opportunity to participate in the economic and social life of his or her country; in a similar way, Hegel sees equality before the law as the crucial achievement of modernity, for which he saw the French Revolution as breakthrough.
The question then is, of course, how this relates to inequality of income and wealth. Smith and Hegel do not give us formula for how much inequality is compatible with the equal standing of citizens. Roughly, Smith thinks that free markets lead to greater equality because they lift the working poor to a comfortable standard of living and they erode the inequalities of the feudal age, and that’s one of the reasons why he endorses them. Hegel, in contrast, thinks that free markets lead to increasing inequality; in fact, he predicts the development of a “rabble” of poor who cannot lift themselves out of poverty any more. This is an aporia in Hegel’s account that he never quite resolves.

So Hegel would not have been surprised by Picketty’s arguments, although Hegel himself does not have a developed theory of capital. Smith, I think, would have to ask himself whether he would have to revise basic assumptions of his model. He was very interested in empirical data, however, and so I assume he would have been happy to do so.

 

3:AM:I guess one of the things that Piketty is warning us about is the return to a belle-epoque type of economic reality where inherited unearned capital is the dominant form of making money and the source of the vast inequalities. Does this non-commerce market capitalism change the requirements for theorizing markets?

LH:It is sort of ironic that Picketty warns us about falling back into a situation that is very much the one against which Smith developed his model of commercial society as an alternative: a form of feudalism in which a small class of privileged individuals holds disproportionate wealth and disproportionate power, which helps them to cement their position. Smith was too optimistic, it seems, with his assumption that in a commercial society vast fortunes would be eroded over time. Picketty suggests progressive taxation as a remedy; I think Smith would have been far less opposed to this than many of those who claim his name today. But he would also have asked, I guess, whether there aren’t other levers that can, and should, be moved, for example concerning a wider distribution of capital ownership.

It is worth noting that the markets we have today are really different kinds of animals than the markets Smith wrote about, for example when it comes to the role of corporations, or when you consider the network effects that you have in many modern technologies. The problem with many markets today is that they are far less open for new entrants than the rhetoric of “free markets” suggests. But this was what Smith very much cared about. I am working on a paper in which I argue that it is actually misleading to use the metaphor of “trickling down” (which I still use in the book) for the way in which Smith thinks about markets. The mechanism he is interested in is much more a question of giving individuals an opportunity to “work their way up”, as it were. He cared about the creation of jobs, about individuals being able to acquire a small fortune and hence economic security, which would give them “tranquillity of the mind”. So the question would be: which institutional settings do we need today to make sure that every individual can earn a decent standard of living, and have sufficient economic security – so that people can turn to those things in life that really matter. For Smith, these are not economic things, but things such love and friendship, and time to enjoy literature or music. Hegel would have agreed, by the way.

3:AM:Where do you stand on the Smith/Hegel divide? Are you sympathetic to Hegelian Dionysian forces or are you more with Adam Smith?

LH:I think there isn’t one picture of the market that captures all its aspects; different markets can have very different features in different situations, sometimes as benign as Smith thought, but also often as disruptive as Hegel thought, or anything in between. What is important to note, however, is that since the times in which Smith and Hegel wrote we have learned much more about the ways in which markets, rather than being “natural”, depend on institutional and cultural preconditions, with legal preconditions playing a particularly important role.

Smith and Hegel assume that the property rights that underlie markets are fairly unified, which is understandable given that they wrote at a time when many of the things for which we have property rights and markets today did not exist. I am thinking in particular about financial markets, on which I work on at the moment. Katharina Pistor, a law professor at Columbia University, has done extremely interesting work on how financial markets are legally constructed (see here). If we want to understand markets, and in particular financial markets, from a broad philosophical perspective, including a normative perspective, we need to talk about these things as well.

3:AM:Aristotle never wrote a book on economics. Ernest Gellner quipped that the mystery is not that Aristotle didn’t but that Adam Smith did. Do you think there’s a need for economics to recalibrate itself so that it is less reliant on models that missed the recent crisis and seems to miss the dimensions your position requires?

LH:At the moment, I am fairly optimistic about many developments in economic theorizing, especially among the younger generation of economists. Pickety’s plea for understanding economics as a social science might help things to move along more quickly into this direction: more empirical, more strongly historically situated. But I think there is still some resistance among economists to also engage with normative approaches. What we need is an integrated, interdisciplinary approach to markets, which includes economic, sociological, psychological, historical and philosophical insights – ideally, such an approach can lead to suggestions about how to improve the institutional framework of markets, but also the institutions that we need to correct and embed markets. The academic division of labour has many advantages, but we also need to get together, from time to time, to integrate crucial insights and to learn from one another. This is hard work, and the incentive structures within academia do not reward it very highly. But that shouldn’t deter us!

One thing to note, however, is that many things that are blamed on “markets” or on “the economy” actually have to do with the way in which large organizations – in the sense of Weber’s “bureaucracies”, roughly – function, and what’s going on in them. Think, for example, about the diffusion of responsibility: this can take place in markets, but also within organizations. Philosophers have not paid much attention to how organizations shape the moral agency of individuals, maybe because of the division between moral philosophy, which mainly looks at single individuals, and political philosophy, which looks at public institutions. But there is this whole realm of phenomena in between: the way in which we act as the infamous “cog in the wheel” when we act from within our organizational roles. Thinking about markets, and about Smith and Hegel, has led me to thinking about organizations: the ways in they support or undermine the moral agency of individuals, and the additional moral problems they pose, simply by the fact that they are organizations. My next book project is about the way in which individual agency and organizational structures are interrelated, and how organizational practices can function in ways that are morally justified.

3:AM:So, tell us more about your new project.

LH:It’s a basic fact about human nature – one that Smith and Hegel were very much aware of – that we are influenced by our social contexts. But arguably, Smith and Hegel still believed that there is some kind of natural or metaphysical process underlying the development of these contexts (and scholars disagree, of course, how exactly to understand them on these counts). If we don’t believe in these things, the question becomes: how can we shape our social contexts in ways that allow us to become, and remain, moral agents? Which co-responsibilities do we have for these phenomena, which, by definition, transcend the scope of action of single individuals?

Organizations are one area in which these questions arise, and I think they arise with particular urgency today, because organizations are so important for modern societies – if they function well, they can be extraordinarily effective, but if things go wrong, they can go wrong on a really large scale, not only with regard to how direct stakeholders are treated, but also with regard to effects on the wider society. There is some work in business ethics on organizations, but it is not very well connected to the philosophical debate, and there is a lot of organizational theory, of course, but it mostly considers organizations from a functional perspective, without taking into account their moral dimension. And there are indeed many moral dimensions; I did a series of qualitative interviews with people who work in different organizations when I started this project, and the stories they told me were absolutely fascinating – about alienation and recognition, about being torn whether to use immoral means for moral purposes, about gaming the system in order to protect colleagues, etc. I now try to develop a framework in which I can connect these insights to philosophical debates: about how to deal with rules, about the moral responsibility for handling information, about the ways in which one can reflect about one’s professional role. And about the ways in which organizations can make sure that they fulfill their own moral duties, and help their members to fulfill theirs.

3:AM:And for the readers at 3:AM are there five boks other than your own that we should read to get further into your fascinating philosophical world?

LH:If you haven’t already read them, both Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentimentsand Hegel’s Philosophy of Rightare fantastic reads! In terms of more contemporary work on markets and organizations, two recent books that I found very inspiring are Mark R. Reiff, Exploitation and Economic Justice in the Liberal Capitalist State(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2013) and Christopher McMahon, Public Capitalism. The Political Authority of Corporate Executives(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2013). And as I currently teach a class on Arendt, I cannot resist recommending her The Human Condition, it’s such a fascinating book, full of inspiring insights about how one might think about the place of human beings in the world and about the different aspects of our “vita activa.”

+++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++

https://www.3-16am.co.uk/articles/the-monarchy-of-fear?c=end-times-archive

 

The Monarchy of Fear


Interview by Richard Marshall.

 

In an absolute monarchy, the monarch thrives on fear, and usually finds many ways to engineer fear. But in a democracy we need to look one another in the eye as equals and to work together for common goals. This requires trust, the willingness to be vulnerable to what other people do. If I’m always defending myself against you I do not trust you. Trust breeds deceit and defensiveness rather than common efforts to solve problems.

As Rawls says, the way to prevent envy from damaging democracy is, above all, by a social safety net so that everyone is assured of having all sorts of important good things. Then there may still be envy, but it will be much less toxic. But in a climate where fear is rampant, that security won’t be there, and then envy, too, will run wild.’

Gandhi was, as Richard Sorabji shows in his marvelous book, very close to the Stoics in his normative views. So he thought one should deal with fear by just getting rid of it. For me the problem of fear is much more complicated, because where you have love you will rightly have fear.

Martha C. Nussbaumis the Ernst Freund Distinguished Service Professor of Law and Ethics, appointed in the Law School and Philosophy Department. She is an Associate in the Classics Department, the Divinity School, and the Political Science Department, a Member of the Committee on Southern Asian Studies, and a Board Member of the Human Rights Program.

Professor Nussbaum is internationally renowned for her work in Ancient Greek and Roman philosophy, feminist philosophy, political philosophy, and philosophy and the arts and is actively engaged in teaching and advising students in these subjects. She has received numerous awards and honorary degrees and is the author of many books and articles. Here she discusses her latest book ‘The Monarchy of Fear.’

 

3:AM: You’ve written about the emotion of fear in US politics today. First can you sketch for us what you take this fear to be about, both on the left and the right?

Martha Nussbaum:On the right, fear is about the “American Dream,” the idea that your children will do better than you did. Lower middle-class income stagnation and the way that automation and technological change have changed the nature of employment — while college education is ever more costly — lead to a sense of helplessness in that group, manifest in declining health status. On the left, people had a sense that we were moving in the right direction under Obama, but were still very worried about economic inequality. Now, under Trump, people are much more worried about that, and worried anew about race and gender issues that seemed to be doing better before.

3:AM: So why do you say that fear is particularly bad for democratic government rather than all forms of government? Is it because you see it as eroding trust, and democracies need trust more than other forms of government?

MN:Exactly. In an absolute monarchy, the monarch thrives on fear, and usually finds many ways to engineer fear. But in a democracy we need to look one another in the eye as equals and to work together for common goals. This requires trust, the willingness to be vulnerable to what other people do. If I’m always defending myself against you I do not trust you. Trust breeds deceit and defensiveness rather than common efforts to solve problems. So the infantile reflex of running for comfort to an all-powerful figure is a great danger to democracy, as is the flip side of that fear, also infantile, the need to control other people. Babies can’t work with other people, they can only enforce their will by yelling. That is why Freud referred to the infant as “His Majesty the Baby.” Not a good model for democratic citizenship.

3:AM:Why is it fear that you pick out as the main emotion? Why not anger, for example?

MN:I devote a lot of space in the book to other emotions: a chapter each on anger, disgust, envy, and hope. But my new idea is that fear, which is likely the earliest emotion genetically and the most primitive in evolutionary terms, lies behind all the others and infuses them, rendering them politically toxic. When we feel terrified and powerless, for example, we often try to reestablish control by blaming and scapegoating others. A great deal of political anger is fed by fear. So what I do is to separate a healthy aspect of anger, namely protesting real wrongs, from an unhealthy aspect, retributive zeal for pain. I show how Dr. King made that same separation when he asked the angry members of his movement to “purify” and “channelize” their anger: they ought to protest, but not in a spirit of retributive payback. Rather their protest should look forward with hope and faith to common work.

 

3:AM: And what’s the connection between the emotionsof envy, hatred and anger in politics?

MN:Envy (and everyone should look at John Rawls’s marvelous analysis of it, one of the most neglected parts of A Theory of Justice) is a painful emotion caused by noticing that others have the good things of life and you don’t, AND you feel despair and powerlessness about getting them by your own efforts. You therefore want to spoil the other party’s enjoyment of those good things. That emotion often leads to aggression, but it is not the same as anger, since anger requires the thought that the other person has done something bad to you. A good way to see this difference is to think of Aaron Burr, both in history and in Miranda’s wonderful depiction in Hamilton.

Here’s Hamilton, creative and beloved, “in the room where it happens.” And Burr feels powerless to get into that charmed circle by his own efforts. Hamilton hasn’t done anything to him, so he has no basis for anger, but he really wants Hamilton to disappear. The challenge to the duel was so odd because it didn’t really have any cogent accusation: it was pure envy. As Rawls says, the way to prevent envy from damaging democracy is, above all, by a social safety net so that everyone is assured of having all sorts of important good things. Then there may still be envy, but it will be much less toxic. But in a climate where fear is rampant, that security won’t be there, and then envy, too, will run wild.

3:AM: The third emotion you connect to anger in politics, alongside anger and envy, is disgust. How do you see the connections?

MN:Disgust is an emotion whose content is a refusal to be contaminated by substances that remind us of our animal mortality. (This is the result of a lot of detailed experimental work by Paul Rozin and others, which I describe in the book.) Its primary objects are feces, most bodily fluids, and corpses. But in every known society these primary disgust-properties, bad smell, decay, hyper-animality, are projected onto some group of people in a way that subordinates them: these are the animals, not we. These people have dirty animal bodies. We can see this reflex in so many different forms — racial hatred of African-Americans, the Indian caste hierarchy, disgust for women’s bodily fluids, and, as I’ve written elsewhere, disgust for gays and lesbians, which has been a primary source of homophobia. This “projective disgust” is already a type of fear, since it is a set of deceptive stratagems to avoid facing the dominant group’s own animality and mortality. And it can aid and abet political hatred, because if you see the other as basically an animal, it is much easier to countenance aggressive actions and policies. We see this sort of fear-driven disgust in today’s discourse about immigrants, in the resurgence of unashamed racial hatred, and in the widespread use of disgust rhetoric to denigrate women.

3:AM: How does your analysis help us understand racism and sexism and misogyny – you argue, for example, for a distinction between sexism and misogyny and find misogyny is much more strongly connected with anger, disgust and envy than just sexism don’t you?

MN:I devote an entire chapter to sexism and misogyny, partly because this was such a prominent theme in the recent campaign, partly because this case shows how fear, anger, disgust, and envy all come together, and partly because an important new book of feminist philosophy, Kate Manne’s Down Girl, had just appeared and I wanted to make her important arguments known to other people. Manne argues that there are two different things, to which she gives the names “sexism” and “misogyny,” aware that this doesn’t perfectly track ordinary usage, but there are two distinct phenomena to which we can somewhat artificially give these two different names. Sexism is a set of beliefs about female inferiority. Misogyny is, by contrast, an enforcement mechanism, a set of practical strategies for keeping women in their place. Her excellent point is that misogyny does not require sexism, and indeed often is all the more pronounced and intense when people sense or know that women are indeed equal in ability: otherwise what need of all the efforts to keep them out?

I accept this distinction, and I also accept one further diagnosis by Manne: that misogyny is driven by a kind of fear-infused anger that women are getting out of their traditional place and claiming men’s place. “They” are taking “our” jobs. The title of the book refers to what you say to an obstreperous dog: “down”, get back in your place. But I say that things are actually more complicated, since misogyny also feeds on envy at women’s astonishing success in education, a worldwide phenomenon, and also on disgust, a time-honored theme in discussion of women’s bodies. Sexism, as you say, is not so connected with any of these things. No reason for anxiety in sexism: if women can’t do X or Y or Z, they just won’t do it. But typically people put up all sorts of artificial barriers to women’s activity, even in sports — think of all the outrage against women who wanted to run marathons! And that was very likely because, deep down, people knew that women COULD run marathons, and maybe those same women would not want to stay at home with ten children.

3:AM: You end on an optimistic note, discussing aspects of hope, love and faith in humanity that are the good emotions we need to guide us rather than the bad ones. What is so nourishing and good about these emotions and how do they important for democratic governments?

MN:Well, they are not good in all circumstances. People with bad causes nourish these same emotions. But if a cause is good, we need hope to energize us. Here I draw on another excellent recent book by the philosopher Adrienne Martin, a philosophical analysis of hope. Again I do not agree with everything, but here’s the basic idea. Hope and fear are understood to be very similar: the Stoics always said that they went together because both relied on attachment to uncertain things. Where you have reason to fear you will have reason to hope. And what Martin contributes is an argument that it isn’t a question of the probabilities. You can have fear even though success is quite likely (think of great actors who have stage fright), and you can have hope even when a loved one’s illness has a very bad prognosis.

The difference is your attitude and how the emotion is bound up with action tendencies. Hope gets you going doing hopeful things. I accept that, and then I turn to Kant. Kant said that we have an obligation to act to make our world better. But in order to get ourselves going we need hope. So, we have an obligation to get ourselves into an attitude of practical hope, to support our efforts to do good. I believe that, and think there are things we can do to shift our perspective from seeing the glass as half empty to seeing it as half full. I suggest that this is always a personal matter but there are “practices of hope” that seem useful to me, some for some people, others for others: the arts, religion, protest movements, Socratic philosophy (a school of respectful interchanges), and various other types of local civic engagement. I also recommend a mandatory national service program for young people, so that our young people, usually so de facto segregated from people who differ by race and class, will go out into their country and learn about it, meanwhile doing useful work such as elder care and child care.o Other countries have tried this, and their problems of social ignorance are usually less troubling than ours.

By love I mean what Dr. King meant: not liking people as friends, but having good will toward them as human beings, even while one may protest against their actions; being ready to work with them for the common good. And by faith I again mean what he meant, an attitude of patient hopeful expectation, not of utopia, but of gradual change for the better.

3:AM:You’ve argued elsewhere that we can benefit from understanding philosophy as therapeutic in the Hellenistic manner. Is this work on the monarchy of fear you putting into practice this Helenistic therapeutic approach? Could you sketch for us what you take this approach to be, and why you say we really can’t understand later great philosophers such as Spinoza and Descartes without understanding the Romans and the Greeks?

MN:The Hellenistic thinkers (the Epicureans, Stoics, and Skeptics) all thought that philosophy should be not merely theoretical, but also practical. They also thought that one primary role for philosophy to play was to offer a critique of problematic emotions. But then they differ in how this comes about. The Stoics, like Aristotle, think that people should be in charge of their own critical thinking and should address their own emotions with introspection but also with good rational arguments that can be shared with others. This is the approach I follow.

I criticize the other two schools for making pupils too subservient to the wisdom of a dogmatic leader. There are then all sorts of things the Stoics offer us that are useful today, and that greatly influenced early modern Western philosophy. They were great thinkers about the nature and structure of emotions. They were great thinkers about logic, about the philosophy of language, about knowledge, about ethics. So when I say that early modern thinkers can’t be fully understood without the Stoics, I mean all of those things. Often puzzling locutions in Descartes or Spinoza become clear as day once we see that they are using technical terms of the Stoics, and so forth.

 

3:AM: Is your approach to fear a version of Stoicism– with a number of gaps filled in so to speak? What did the Stoics say about the emotions and why did you think there were four gaps that needed to be dealt with before it could be comprehensive?

MN:All right, here we need to make a big distinction: between the Stoics’ descriptive theory of what emotions are, and their normative theory of what we ought to do about them. I accept the descriptive theory with many modifications, but I reject the normative theory. The descriptive theory says that emotions are evaluative appraisals that always ascribe to things outside a person’s own control great importance for a person’s own flourishing. I think this is basically correct and deeply insightful. However, as you say, in Upheavals in ThoughtI identified four gaps. The first is that since this theory survives only in fragments, it must simply be made much more systematic and elaborate.

Second, however, we must reject the Stoics’ notion that only human adults have emotions, and we must adjust the theory to make room for the evident fact that animals have all kinds of emotions. So the theory can’t be based upon language, or hold that emotions are propositional attitudes. The evaluative appraisals must be understood as value-laden perceptions. Third, the Stoics didn’t investigate the ways in which different cultures shape emotions differently, so we must so so, aided by anthropology and history. Fourth, the Stoics lacked interest in infancy and childhood and did not describe the development of emotions over time, so we must also do that — aided by both psychoanalysis and literature (Proust is a big figure in that part of my book).

As for the normative theory: the Stoics thought that people simply should wean themselves from all attachments to things outside their own rational will, and that way they would get rid of all the emotions. I think that they were right to urge people not to be hung up on money and power, but totally wrong when they asked them not to be deeply attached to loved ones, family, children, and also one’s own country or city or whatever. When Cicero’s daughter died in childbirth and the Roman Republic was collapsing into tyranny, Cicero said he was grieving profoundly because he had lost the two things that he loved most in the world. But his Stoic buddies didn’t like that. They thought he should just get over it! So I think that the Stoics are mostly wrong, though about anger they have some extremely valuable insights.

Gandhi was, as Richard Sorabji shows in his marvelous book, very close to the Stoics in his normative views. So he thought one should deal with fear by just getting rid of it. For me the problem of fear is much more complicated, because where you have love you will rightly have fear. So the struggle with fear becomes a subtle one of separating good from bad, healthy from unhealthy. If we keep fear in our lives, we have to beware of demagogues who manipulate fear.

 

3:AM: How does thinking about the emotions across a range of capabilities reinforce attachment to all the norms a liberal western democracy requires and although consideration of psychology in political thinking in the western tradition is rare are there other philosophical political traditions where psychology and emotions in particular are important?

MN:I have no idea why you say consideration of psychology is “rare” in the western tradition. Here are some of the Western thinkers who devoted a large part of their work to the analysis of emotions and desires: Plato, Aristotle,all the Hellenistic thinkers Greek and Roman, Aquinas, Descartes, Spinoza, Hume, Adam Smith, Hutcheson, William James. What happened was that for a century or so, the topic was eclipsed — partly owing to the great influence of the view of William James that emotions are simply perceptions of a bodily change. But in part, too, the avoidance was cultural: British philosophy of the twentieth century was reticent and squeamish about all sorts of important human topics. So it took courageous pioneers to reopen the topic: Anthony Kenny, George Pitcher, and then gradually a whole generation of younger philosophers flooded in, undismayed by the “messiness” of the topic. This good development was greatly aided by the rediscovery of ancient Greek and Roman philosophy.

I don’t think that thinking about emotions helps reinforce attachment to liberal political norms, To support those we need independent normative arguments. But once we are attached to them, we’d better understand the emotions or we won’t get and/or keep them. Emotions give us both resources and problems: we need to see clearly what problems lie before us and what good ingreadients of the personality we can draw on. If you want people to sacrifice for something beyond themselves, you need to know how to appeal to an extended compassion, as FDR did in commending the New Deal. If you want people to protest without retributive anger, as King did, you had better understand anger deeply, as he did. If you ignore disgust, you will miss a large impediment to human equality.

I am not as well educated about non-western traditions as I ought to be. I know that the study of emotions is important in Chinese philosophy, but I don’t know much about it. In Indian philosophy, which I know somewhat more, it is terribly important, both in aesthetics and in ethics. The Buddhist philosopher Santideva is one of the greatest writers about anger. And the nineteenth/ twentieth-century Indian thinker Rabindranath Tagore (1861-1941) is one of the greatest modern thinkers about the emotions and their role, both in political life and in education.

+++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++

 
 

Philosophy as the great naïveté


Jason Stanleyinterviewed by Richard Marshall.

Jason Stanley is a multi-groove philosopher at Rutgers. He translated some Fregewith Richard Heck. He wrote a cool book Knowledge and Practical Interestsand last year a brain-boning book Know Howthat lames the virtue epistemology and ethics tradition started way back with the Ancient Greeks. He thinks philosophy is perpetual crisis. For many he is to philosophy what Ocarina of Timeis to video games.

3:AM:You have strong views about philosophy in general, in particular the public perception of its place in the academic curriculum. You wrote a piece ‘The Crisis of Philosophy’where you said that in America at least the place of philosophy in the humantities was unclear. You’ve been engaged in a number of high profile defences of the subject, from the New York Timesto the rousing debatewith Carlin Romano. Can you say why you think there’s a suspicion of philosophy, and a kind of crisis and why you defend the important place of philosophy in our culture?

Jason Stanley:There has always been a suspicion of philosophy, dating back to Socrates. The talk of “crisis” falsely suggests that there is something new about the issue of the relevance of philosophical work. Hannah Arendtis right when she describes as unavoidable the question, “How can anything relevant for the world we live in arise out of so resultless an enterprise?” There is also no new crisis in the discipline. Philosophy itself is and ought to be in continual crisis.

There are areas of philosophy that have obvious relevance for the world we live in. For example, it’s obvious that Doug Husak’s work has extrinsic value – he uses philosophical reasoning to criticize the prison industrial complex, the great moral failing of our country. But ethics and philosophy of law are not my areas. I have spent my life thinking about knowledge, representation, and intelligent action, and I hold out the perhaps naïve hope that a greater understanding of the capacities that make humans distinctive in the world will end up having relevance beyond simply an expanded self-understanding.

I’m also engaging in philosophy when I write about the value of philosophy. There is a grand tradition of skepticism about my field – Humeand even more clearly Nietzschzecome to mind. It’s sad that there are no current sophisticated defenders of that tradition with whom to engage, because it’s healthy for philosophers to be forced to defend the worldly relevance of what they are doing. The fact that I work on questions that do not have obviousextrinsic value makes the intellectual challenge more formidable. But I think that my philosophical work is better because I take this intellectual challenge seriously.

That said, I do think the estrangement between philosophy and our fellow humanities takes a particular form right now. There has been genuine progress in neighboring areas in the humanities. The progress has come through the realization of how much of the traditional humanities was done from a specific empowered, privileged perspective, either a white European male perspective, or from the perspective of the state and not its inhabitants, and the realization of how taking such a perspective skewed the work. Think, for example, of the time in the 1960s when it became clear to historians, via belated recognition of the work of Du Bois, that historical research on the Reconstruction era in the south was largely inaccurate, and the inaccuracies were due to underlying racial biases of the historians. In almost every humanities discipline, there are examples like this – cases in which it was realized that biased perspectives resulted in shoddy and inaccurate work or scholarship. The recognition of the pervasive nature of implicit (or explicit) bias in perspective, and the recognition that such bias impedes truth-seeking enterprises was an important moment in intellectual culture. But it left the discipline of philosophy relatively untouched. That has created an even wider than usual gulf between the rest of the humanities and philosophy.

Finally, as I emphasized in my Inside Higher Educationpiece, there is an additional difference between philosophy and the humanities, one that is less profound but nevertheless equally divisive. Our fellow humanists write aboutnovelists and artists and musicians. In contrast, the intellectual life of most philosophers is closer to that of novelists and artists and musicians than people who study novelists and artists. There is great naïveté in the ambition to write the great American novel, naïveté that is mirrored in the ambition to solve some of the long-standing philosophical questions once and for all. It’s utterly natural to view someone who is trying to write the great American novel, or is trying to explain once and for all how autonomous action is possible, as not only naïve but also ignorant (of the greatest of Melville, or the greatness of Kant). So there really is a cultural divide between the vast majority of humanists and the majority of philosophers.

3:AM:One of the things that will support your defence of philosophy is getting more people to see what you and your peers are doing. It’s sometimes difficult for those outside the discipline to get a grip on the geography of what’s going on that’s important at the moment. Eric Schwitzgebel‘s just posted on his blogabout how there can be philosophy of more or less anything, even dating, which kind of makes the point about how difficult it is to know where to look. Philosophy of language is perhaps where you are best situated so perhaps you could give a broad outline of what the main issues are in that domain at the moment. I love your comment about your piece on philosophy of language in the 20th Century for Routledgewhere you say, “I attempt to summarize philosophy of language in the Twentieth Century. It’s a completely absurd task, and I fail miserably.” We’ll take another failure if its as good as that one!

JS:Let me begin by responding to your points about the relative accessibility of philosophical work. Even topics the significance of which is obvious to the lay public involve arguments that will stretch the patience of the lay public. For example, the significance of the topic of consciousness is very easy for the lay public to understand. But the best work on even this topic involves stretches of reasoning that are dauntingly complex. The conclusions David Chalmers’ draws from his views are accessible and sexy to the public. But the views of content he has that support these conclusions are deep, complex, and subtle. They are certainly not accessible to the lay public. It’s the arguments he gives that make him a great philosopher, rather than the accessibility of his conclusions.

As Peter Ludlowemphasized in his comments at the Philosophical Progress conference at Harvard, philosophers need to introduce terminology that may not have pre-established usage. A successful definition carves up conceptual space the right way. This makes philosophical work, like mathematical work, terminologically heavy. Mathematical progress depends in part on arriving at the right sort of definitions – what Fregein The Foundations of Arithmeticcalled “fruitful definitions” (the example Frege gives is that of the continuity of a function). Philosophical progress is no different. Both mathematics and philosophy are difficult to access, because they are terminology heavy in similar ways.

Philosophy of language is particularly close to mathematics in this regard, because of how close it is to mathematical logic. As I emphasized in my piece on philosophy of language in the 20th century, philosophy of language has made so many advances because of the advances in logic in the late 19th and early 20th century. Developments in logic, and in particular model-theoretic semantics, gave impetus to the discipline, and its sibling empirical discipline in linguistics, formal semantics. Right now, there is a large body of researchers sprawled across philosophy, linguistics, and computer science (and perhaps psychology as well) working on similar topics. For example, if you take Rutgers as an example, the leading program in philosophy of language in the world, you see that our semantics research group has active faculty members in linguistics, computer science, and philosophy. I would describe the principal goal of all of our work, as with my own research in the philosophy of language, to be devoted to figuring out how much of linguistic interpretation is due to convention, and how much is due to general knowledge about the world.

There was a trend in the philosophy of language starting in the 1970s to argue that what appeared to be due to linguistic conventions was in fact due to knowledge about the world and general reasoning. Probably, this divorced philosophical work on linguistic representation from thought about representation elsewhere in the humanities, where theorists were looking for symbol-like representational systems everywhere. Philosophy of language instead was devoted to emphasizing how little conventionality played a role in linguistic communication. As I have also pointed out in the essay you mention, this was the result of quite accidental sociological features of the discipline – because of the titanic influence of Saul Kripke’s work, in the 1970s and the 1980s the focus of the discipline was on defending the view that proper names that had the same reference, such as “Mark Twain” and “Samuel Clemens”, had the same conventional meaning. A lot of energy in the discipline was devoted to defending this thesis. There was interesting work done here, but also some stagnation. There was a sort of template for writing a philosophy of language paper for several decades – start with an interesting phenomenon that seems to reveal complex conventionality (like the difference in meaning between “Mark Twain” and “Samuel Clemens”, or the fact that “Every beer is in the fridge” can convey different things in different contexts), and argue that really the symbol system itself gives us very little guidance in interpretation. This really isolated the philosophy of language from many disciplines – both the humanities at large, and linguistic semantics, and even formal pragmatics in linguistics, where people were interested precisely in investigating the special features of the symbolic system.

In the mid-to-late 1990s, a group of philosophers of language with training in linguistics started to reverse the trend, and focus on the special, quirky properties of symbolic systems. As a result, philosophy of language has emerged from its relative isolation. Because the focus in philosophy of language was for so long on arguing what the symbolic system didn’tdo, there was a lot of catching up to do. A lot of the interesting topics and developments, such as research into the meaning of questions, had moved into linguistic semantics, where it was a bit divorced from philosophical concerns. Now, there is a great deal of excitement in the field, as people have realized that there is so much more complexity to linguistic meaning that we had realized. Philosophers such as Elizabeth Camphave started to see that there is a case to be made that phenomena that seemed obviouslynot conventional in nature, such as sarcasm, might be conventional after all. The discovery by Andy Egan, John Hawthorne, and Brian Weathersonthat epistemic modals – terms like “might” as they occur in a sentence like “It might be raining outside now” (said by someone ignorant of the weather) – behave in ways very different than standard models of meaning would predict have led to the thought that a new model of meaning might be required. Motivated by the complex properties of very simple words, philosophers and linguistic semanticists have started to formulate new theories of content, giving new life to old programs such as expressivism. So it’s a very exciting time in the philosophy of language, and has been for about a dozen years.

For a long time, philosophers of language had thought that there was nothing foundational to be learned anymore from detailed work on particular constructions in language. We have now learned that this is false. Thinking intensely about the meaning of words like “might” or “if”, or the relation between the meaning of questions and declarative sentences, has led to really interesting discoveries. We are at the beginning, rather than at the end, of inquiry into the complex properties of the distinctive representational system that is natural language.

knowhow

3:AM:Now one of the subjects that you keep returning to is Ryle’s distinction between knowing that and knowing how. Before you tell us about your argument which I believe is to say that knowing how is a species of knowing that, can you say what’s at stake here. I think sometimes one of the problems for outsiders is that they don’t pick up on the large and important issues that the detailed arguments are then engaged in sorting out.

JS:There are two ways to look at my new book. The first is that I am using a defense of thesis that knowing how to do something is knowledge of a truth to shed light on the notion of knowledge. The second is that I am using a defense of the thesis that knowing how to do something is knowledge of a truth to shed light on the nature of knowledge how and related notions such as skill.

Philosophy, and indeed broader intellectual culture, is in the grip of a false conception of factual knowledge, one that is antithetical to much recent work in epistemology. Once one has the correct externalist conception of knowledge, a dichotomy between practical and theoretical knowledge starts to look dubious. To use an example Robert Stalnakersuggested to me, think of my knowledge that the code to an alarm is 17-32-14. I may not be able to tell you what the combination is – I just can type into the alarm pad. The knowledge resides, so to speak, in my fingers. But it’s still propositional knowledge – I know that the code to the alarm is 17-32-14, I just can’t tell you. One reason the conclusions of Know Howmatter is that they free us from a constraining and misleading picture of propositional knowledge.

A second reason the conclusions of Know Howmatter is that they shed light on how much of skilled action is due to learning information about the world. Knowledge how to do something is a large part (or maybe all of) skill. I can only be skilled at basketball if I know how to play basketball. If I am right that knowledge of how to do something amounts to learning a truth, then we learn that skilled action requires learning something about the world. Even if I’m right, the question is open as to how much of the acquisition of a skill is acquiring information about the world. Does knowledge exhaust skill, or is skill knowledge together with something else? What about improvements in skill? Does that amount to additional knowledge about the world? There are a whole set of questions and positions about the notion of skill that are opened up here.

It is of the utmost importance for philosophy to gain greater clarity on what is involved in acquiring a skill, since skill and competence plays such a central role in so many philosophical projects. For example, virtue epistemologists hold that propositional knowledge relies on skills – think of the appeal to competence in the work of, for example, Ernest Sosa. The appeal to skill in Sosa’s work has a reductive character – knowledge requires competence, and competence itself does not presuppose knowledge. It is important that competence does not presuppose knowledge, since competence, for the virtue epistemologist, halts the regress of justification. If knowledge how is propositional knowledge, many if not all versions of virtue epistemology are imperiled.

There are many other uses of the notion of skill in philosophy that will need to be rethought if the conclusions of my book are correct. Philosophers have typically assumed that knowing how and skill are not propositional knowledge states, and used these notions in their theories. Generally, the pattern of argument is to establish some connection between the target notion to be analyzed – be it linguistic understanding, virtue, knowledge, or perception – and knowing how. The assumption that knowing how is a non-propositional state is then brought in to solve some kind of problem, e.g. to halt a regress, or to provide a reductive, non-factual basis for something. There are projects in epistemology, in ethics, in philosophy of mind, and philosophy of language that have this character. In general, if I’m right, all of these philosophical projects have to be rethought.

The topic of the relation between knowing how to do something and factual knowledge is not local to philosophy. It has been picked up by many disciplines. For example, it is a label for a distinction in artificial intelligence, and is thought to mirror a fundamental distinction in cognitive neuroscience, between procedural and declarative knowledge. My book takes up all of these issues. For example, in chapter 7, I argue that the cognitive neuroscientific discussion of declarative knowledge is muddled. And obviously, many disciplines care about the notion of skill. The thesis of my book bears on all of this work.

3:AM:Another area of interest is that of the role of context in making meaning. Your book of essays, Langauge in Contextcontains a treasure trove of your thoughts on this area. Again, though, I wonder if you could just lay out why this is an  important issue outside of philosophy before we look at some of your arguments?

JS:My work in the philosophy of language is devoted to preserving a certain view of linguistic representation. Think of a basic non-linguistic act of communication, such as a tap on the shoulder or a kick under the table. We do not interpret what is communicated by such acts by applying highly specific rules to structured representations. Interpreting such acts does not involve much convention. Instead, we rely on our general knowledge about the world, together with facts about the context in which the act is performed. Prima facie, linguistic communication is different. With linguistic communication, we rely on conventions governing the representations we employ. But there is a lot of reliance on general world knowledge and facts about the context of use even in linguistic communication. So the context-dependence of what is communicated by an utterance of a sentence provides an argument that linguistic communication and non-linguistic communication are not so different after all. The purpose of my work on context is to save the prima facie distinction between linguistic communication and non-linguistic communication, in the face of this kind of challenge. In contrast to non-linguistic communication, I argue that the role knowledge of context plays in linguistic understanding, and production, is limited to a few conventional sources. In short, the goal of this work is to preserve a theoretically significant distinction between linguistic and non-linguistic communication.

All of my philosophical interests coalesce around explaining the properties that make humans distinctive. My work in philosophy of language is part of this project. Sophisticated language use is one of the properties that is distinctive of our species. This strongly suggests that it involves a distinctive kind of representational mechanism. This gives me confidence to pursue the difficult details of accounting for the fact that, like non-linguistic communication, it relies on knowledge of facts about the context of use.

I tend to assume in this work that linguistic communication is distinctive in being the application of highly specific (and conventional) rules to structured representations. I tend to assume, for example, that pictorial representation works differently. But the work of Gabriel Greenberg, now a professor of philosophy at UCLA, has shed some doubt in my mind about the distinctiveness claim. He mounts a good case that at least some kinds of pictorial representation involves many of the same features as linguistic representation.

3:AM:You won a top prize for your book Knowledge and Practical Interests. There you claim that my knowing something is dependent on my practical interests. So knowledge turns out to be dependent on how much it matters! This is counter-intuitive – and so exactly what I want from my philosophers! So could you explain this position and why you argue what you do?

JS:My two books about knowledge are connected. Both take on the distinction between the practical and the theoretical. In my first book, I argue that there isn’t the kind of sharp divide between practical and theoretical reasoning that we learned there was in our introductory philosophy classes (when we, for example, discussed Pascal’s Wager). In my second book, I take on the distinction between practical and theoretical knowledge. Both books are in the service of explaining the value of knowledge by connecting knowledge to action.

My specific argument for the stakes-sensitivity of knowledge, the thesis that whether or not you know something at a time is dependent upon how much the knowledge matters to you at that time, has to do with the connections between knowledge and action. For example, if I am right, then if you know something, you can act on it. But whether you can permissibly act on something depends on what is at stake – whether I can act on my belief that there are nuts in my salad depends upon whether I have a fatal allergy to nuts. It is via the connection to action that knowledge gains its dependence on what is at stake.

I deny that the thesis is counter-intuitive. It’s commonsensical to think that if what’s at issue really matters, you need to do more work in order to know something. Knowing that a country poses a threat to the United States requires a huge amount of investigation, if what is at stake is the decision to go to war.

3:AM:Another area that you have intervened in is that of intention in action. There’s been a lot of recent interest in this subject through the book of Essays on Anscombe’s Intentionlast year. It seems as if you take issue with those philosophers who argue for a notion of direct knowledge/action that is incompatible with causation (i.e. those who move away from Davidson’s interpretation. I guess McDowell is the parade case?). It’s something you write about in a dispute with Jennifer Hornsby, a contributor to Anscombe book, in terms of the phenomenology of meaning. Is that right? This is another of these big issues where the stakes are not always made clear to outsiders. But this dispute seems to be about the scope of a scientific causal explanation in human intention. Those arguing for the idea of a ‘direct’ thing outside the scope of a causal relation almost sound like they’re saying we don’t need science or can’t have a scientific explanation of intention. I always feel a bit lost with this because I’m sure that there’s something I’m really missing here. Can you say what you take the big issue is with this and what your take on it is?

JS:My 2005 debate with Jennifer Hornsbyis but one chapter in my overall project of emphasizing the centrality of factual knowledge, properly understood. Hornsby argues that knowledge of meaning is not factual knowledge, but something else, practical knowledge. I argue, against her, that knowledge of meaning is indeed factual knowledge. Again, the significance of this debate is that it bears on the nature of factual knowledge, and the nature of skill. Knowledge of meaning is just one of the battlegrounds in the larger war about whether factual knowledge is what gives us the capacities that make us distinctively human.

3:AM:I think we can see that you are wrestling with core issues that are not orthogonal to the deep, eternal and traditional philosophical questions. We are living in hugely complex times and troubling ones too. The financial crisis, mass inequality, war, eco doom – there’s a hell of a lot out there that seems we need philosophical thinking. What do you think will be the dominant themes, contributions and discoveries of philosophy in the next decade? Where are your interests going next?

JS: I can’t predict where philosophy is going next. Probably that question has as much to do with accidental sociological features of the discipline than anything else. I have been consistently working on a general picture of knowledge and agency for many years now, and increasingly find myself isolated from the hive mind in philosophy.

I have been working for about twelve years on my book on knowing how – which I started as a joint project with Timothy Williamson. I took time out from this project to write my first book (which, as I’ve said, is related). My own work over the next several years will be devoted to exploring some of the consequences of my work, both within philosophy, for the projects of virtue epistemology and virtue ethics, and also the cognitive sciences. For example, I want to continue the research I started in cognitive neuroscience, and in general track the notion of skill across the various disciplines that study it.

However, I am easily distractible. This is why I have published on so many different topics (of course my extensive project in philosophy of language is not connected to my main work in epistemology and action theory). I expect I will continue to do research on a wide variety of topics not directly related to my central philosophical life project. I’m also interested in certain topics in philosophy of language that relate to politics, such as the nature of propaganda (as in my recent New York Timespiece). I have been thinking a lot lately of how politicians and their handlers use the special features of our symbolic system to manipulate us. It’s an interesting enough topic that I can imagine eventually writing something substantial on it.

3:AM:And finally, are there things outside of philosophy itself – such as the arts, novels and so on, that you find a source of inspiration and help. So has there been something you read that has helped shape your perspective on the issues you brood on?

JS:The issues I brood about and the literature I read when I’m not absorbed in philosophy have exclusively to do with man’s inhumanity to man. I’m not yet sure whether philosophy is my refuge, or where I think I will ultimately find the explanation.

++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++

 

Culture: “Armutsbetroffen” (Affected by Poverty) at TD Berlin: Theater for a future without poverty

Director Helge Schmidt has taken on a new topic. #armutsbetroffen tells the story of full-time poverty, which makes those affected ill. Friday columnist Janina Lütt also contributed.

By Elena Philipp

[This article posted on 7/8/2025 is translated from the German on the Internet, https://www.freitag.de/autoren/elena-philipp/armutsbetroffen-am-td-berlin-theater-fuer-eine-zukunft-ohne-armut.]

The costumes of the three actresses are inspired by the Star Trek series, which presents a vision of a just future without poverty.

What is poverty? “When the ice cream truck rings and your child is the only one who doesn’t run over beaming with joy.” When you live in a village and have no social connections because you have no car and no money. Or when the letter from the medical officer says: “The remaining working capacity of the person examined is no longer economically viable.” Poverty affects all aspects of daily life; it means constant stress, permanent deprivation, and it is passed down from generation to generation. Poverty is a full-time job that makes you sick.

Those affected often appear in the independent theater scene as “experts of everyday life.” Their expertise is taken seriously, as they know best about their situation, even without an official job title. Speaking “from poverty,” not about it, is also a concern of the theater production #armutsbetroffen at TD Berlin.

Director Helge Schmidt collaborated on this with authors from a writing project at the University of Duisburg-Essen entitled Alltägliche Armutserfahrungen – Erzählen als politisches Sprechen (Everyday Experiences of Poverty – Narrative as Political Speech). Among the authors is Janina Lütt, who writes in her columns for Freitag about the lack of respect in the debate on universal basic income and malnutrition among children affected by poverty.

Helge Schmidt knew her as a public figure, wrote to her, and Lütt put him in touch with people affected by poverty across the entire spectrum. Contributors include a single mother—often a path to poverty in Germany—a pensioner, and a former high earner who, after a stroke, is now considered “useless human capital.”

The production avoids clichés about poverty

Everyday experiences like hers received widespread attention on Twitter in 2022 under the hashtag #ichbinarmutsbetroffen (I am affected by poverty). Tweets can therefore be found in the play, as well as texts from the Duisburg workshops and excerpts from Janina Lütt’s columns.

Only statistics and meta-analyses are missing, although Helge Schmidt often incorporates sociological and economic perspectives into his research, for example in his documentary play about the Cum-Ex tax scandal or on pharmaceutical profits from cancer drugs. In #armutsbetroffen, he wanted to prevent the autobiographical stories from disappearing behind the numbers, as so often happens in the discussion about poverty.

The production also avoids clichés in the portrayal of poverty in theater, film, and television. “When it comes to poverty, someone is often wearing a ribbed T-shirt and holding a beer can,” summed up scientist and author Francis Seeck, who grew up on welfare and advises theater festivals on classism, in an interview with Zeit Online.

In #armutsbetroffen, the three round carpets on the sparsely furnished stage are official blue, and the curved office lamps are reminiscent of a government office, but there are no other concrete references. There is no dreariness, as was the case in the Kaiserslautern stage version of Christian Barons’ Ein Mann seiner Klasse (A Man of His Class) – a production that walked the fine line “between enlightenment and social pornography,” as the author himself put it. A poor appearance or the sound of domestic violence; nothing could be further from #armutsbetroffen. Lea Kissing’s clearly structured, tidy stage stands rather for the discipline that poverty demands of those affected.

Too busy surviving

Costume designer Sina Brüggeman dresses the three actresses Agnes Decker, Ruth Marie Kröger, and Laura Uhlig in sporty, retro-futuristic outfits inspired by the series Star Trek, which is cited as a vision of a just future without poverty and wealth. Helge Schmidt contrasts the harshness of the lives of those affected by poverty with the humanistic series and sends a message of hope. The focus is on self-told stories based on the genre of auto-sociobiography, on books such as those by Annie Ernaux, Édouard Louis, and Didier Eribon.

Although the texts in #armutsbetroffen reject the socially acceptable accusation of being lazy at the expense of taxpayers, they deal with the hatred and cyberbullying that followed many of those who stepped into the spotlight. But the authors also report on empowerment and self-empowerment. “The hashtag #ichbinarmutsbetroffen (I am affected by poverty) was life-changing,” it says at one point. And one author writes about the power of coming together independently, without the support of, but also without the regulation of, organizations such as Verdi or the Diakonie: “We wanted self-representation by ourselves, for ourselves.”

Janina Lütt also speaks of a “milestone in poverty activism” in the follow-up discussion. When asked about the chances of a project like #armutsbetroffen bringing about structural change in a federal government that is threatening cuts to welfare benefits, Malina, who does not want to give her surname, points to the utopian core of the project. Holger Schoneville, a professor at the University of Duisburg-Essen who co-initiated the writing project, also rejects the idea that those affected by poverty have a duty to act. As Ruth Maria Kröger, speaking on behalf of one of the play’s authors, puts it indignantly: “Why is there no uprising of the poor? Because we are busy surviving.”

+++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++

 

USA: Deadly politics

by Lukas Hermsmeier

[This editorial posted on 7/10/2025 is translated from the German on the Internet, https://www.woz.ch/2528/usa/toedliche-politik/!V5VC1R64KME7.]

 

The budget package passed last Friday in the US will lead to many deaths in the coming years. Because people will lose their health insurance and can no longer afford treatment. Because hospitals and nursing homes will close, creating increasing care deserts. Because cuts to weather services and disaster response will affect warning systems and emergency response. Because medical laboratories will lack the money for research and diseases will spread more quickly. Because refugees will be deported to countries where their lives are in danger. Because the militarization of the police will be pushed further and further and prisons will be filled. Because the end of development aid threatens the livelihoods of fourteen million people. Because the US Army will have more money at its disposal.

Donald Trump wants us to talk about the “Big Beautiful Bill.” Out of journalistic self-respect alone, we should avoid using this name. Left-wing author and activist Astra Taylor calls it the “Debt, Deportation, and Death Bill,” which more accurately describes the consequences of the legislative package: debt, deportations, and death. When it comes to debt, however, the growing national deficit of several trillion US dollars can easily be ignored. As the world’s reserve currency nation, the US has considerable leeway. The real issue is the social emergencies that this package of laws will cause for generations to come. One only has to consider the abandonment of all climate protection measures while simultaneously unleashing fossil fuel production to understand the irreversible devastation that will result.

 

When Donald Trump entered the political arena in 2015, he set himself apart from the other Republican presidential candidates by condemning America’s “endless wars” and ruling out cuts to the welfare state. His portrayal as the savior of the “little guy” was riddled with hypocrisy from the outset, because he pushed through tax breaks for the rich and simply waged the wars at home: against immigrants, trans people, and anyone who isn’t included in “Make America Great Again.” Ten years later, the populist spectacle has been completely emptied of meaning.

Around 11 million Americans could lose their Medicaid health insurance for the poor as a result of the cuts that have now been decided. The tax breaks continue to benefit primarily top earners and large corporations. The US is directly involved in Israel’s war crimes in Gaza and is dropping bombs on Iran and Yemen. Trump is continuing US imperialism; his politics are right-wing class warfare from above. A classic Republican, if you will. Only more fascist, even more anti-democratic.

 

Trump’s program unfolds what Cameroonian philosopher Achille Mbembe has called “necropolitics”: rule over life and death. Some can become doctors, others cannot. Some enjoy the rule of law, others do not. In a country where extreme weather is on the rise while aid infrastructure is being dismantled, not many people are spared from necropolitics. According to the New York Times, last week’s floods in Texas, which killed over a hundred people, might have turned out differently if there had not been extreme government cuts beforehand. While billions upon billions of US dollars are being poured into the deportation regime, important government agencies are understaffed.

“Disaster nationalism” is what Northern Irish author Richard Seymour calls the apocalyptic politics of Trump and other neo-fascists. Disasters are not being counteracted, they are being exploited. More isolation, more surveillance, more repression. Under these circumstances, for many people in the US, one thing will be particularly important between now and the next presidential election in three and a half years: survival.

++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++++

 

Power and its specters: “Through the prism of conspiracy, everything becomes legible again.”

What’s behind it all? An important question, but one that can lead to dangerously simplistic answers, says Donatella Di Cesare. The philosopher explains how belief in conspiracies is linked to feelings of political powerlessness and why she no longer feels free in post-fascist Italy.

[This interview posted on 7/10/2025 is translated from the German on the Internet, https://www.woz.ch/2528/die-macht-und-ihre-gespenster/durch-das-prisma-des-komplotts-wird-alles-wieder-lesbar.]

“The problem arises when questioning skepticism turns into dogmatic certainty,” says Donatella Di Cesare.

WOZ: Donatella Di Cesare, your book “The Conspiracy in Power” was first published in Italian in 2021. Today, it still reads like a diagnosis of the current situation. Why do more and more people believe in powerful conspiracies, i.e., that there is a reality behind reality?

Donatella Di Cesare: Donatella Di Cesare: I wouldn’t talk about a reality behind reality. It’s more a world behind the world that people refer to: the world has a hidden side, a behind-the-scenes world. This concept is crucial to conspiracy theories: people believe in a secret empire where the strings are pulled, where clandestine activities take place, plans are forged, information is manipulated, and thoughts are controlled. The seat of power lies in the occult intrigues of this hidden world. As if by magic, everything there seems clear and enlightened, everything has a solid foundation and a cause. There, one can leave the global disorder behind. Through the prism of conspiracy, everything suddenly becomes legible again.

The courageous philosopher

Donatella Di Cesare is one of Italy’s most important intellectuals. A professor and author of numerous books on philosophy, but also on pressing contemporary issues, she teaches philosophy at La Sapienza University in Rome. She regularly speaks out in political debates. In a talk show on Italian television in 2023, Di Cesare said that Giorgia Meloni’s agriculture minister spoke like a “governatore neo hitleriano”: like a Gauleiter. The minister sued her for defamation. In May 2024, the lawsuit was dismissed by a Rome criminal court. If convicted, the 69-year-old would have faced a prison sentence.

WOZ: Where does this way of thinking come from?

Donatella Di Cesare: It has a long historical tradition. In my book, I try to reconstruct the “primal scene” in literature. From the vast mass of literary texts, three narratives emerge that have acquired mythological significance in the political imagination. They deal with three conspiracies: the Jewish, the Jesuit, and the Masonic. While the Jesuit conspiracy has exhausted itself, the other two overlap and become the “Jewish-Masonic” conspiracy.

WOZ: Can you name any specific literary texts?

Donatella Di Cesare: One story was penned by Hermann O. F. Goedsche, a former Prussian postal secretary who published the very mediocre novel Biarritz in 1868. It contains a chapter entitled “The Rabbi’s Speech.” This chapter was the convoluted source of the “Protocols of the Elders of Zion.” This myth, which triggered and accompanied the Shoah, is still used today to stir up anti-Semitism. I could cite other examples, such as Alexandre Dumas’s Masonic novel “Joseph Balsamo” from 1846/47. In all these stories, the conspiracy always comes from somewhere else. Strangers invade our innermost being: immigrants, migrants, but also bankers, looters, and vagabonds. And behind the scenes, “the Jew” as the stranger of all strangers pulls the strings, hidden, invisible, and intangible, both superhuman and subhuman at the same time.

WOZ: In terms of the history of ideas, would you therefore place the origins of these conspiracy theories in the 19th century, but with lasting consequences for the present?

Donatella Di Cesare: If conspiracy theories were a remnant of the past, they would have to be increasingly exhausted. We see that the opposite is the case. There is an intimate connection between conspiracy and democracy. The keyword “power” can explain this. After the French Revolution, the people were finally sovereign. But where was their power? Previously, it had been concentrated in the body of the king, and now no one knew where to find it again. It seemed temporary and fleeting. The power of the people was the power of no one. This is precisely where Claude Lefort saw the revolutionary aspect of democracy and spoke of a “void in democracy.”

WOZ: What does that mean?

Donatella Di Cesare: There is a lack of foundation, there are divisions, openings: within the democratic community, the people can only declare themselves sovereign in a symbolic sense, not in a substantial and identitarian sense. This means that they cannot occupy the seat of power, which must remain empty. One can understand the amazement of the new democratic citizens faced with this new political form. And one can also understand why this void is filled with all kinds of ghosts. This temptation is greater today than ever before.

WOZ: Why is that?

Donatella Di Cesare: There is no doubt that power today appears increasingly fleeting, omnipresent, networked, and increasingly projected onto the channels of technology and the flows of the economy. It seems to have no center and possibly no direction. It has no face, no name, no place. One senses only its diffuse presence—which further increases uncertainty and suspicion. We infer a cause from the effect. That’s why we feel powerless. We experience this feeling of powerlessness every day. Every evening, we see what’s going on in the world on the news: wars and crises of all kinds. But we have the impression that we can’t change any of it. We are a demos without power, without kratos – in other words, we are no longer a democracy.

WOZ: But if I perceive myself as powerless and then construct a figure who pulls the strings in the background, that doesn’t give me back any power, does it? I remain powerless.

Donatella Di Cesare: I must emphasize that it is usually not just one figure. And there are certainly valid reasons for assuming the existence of this background world. For years, we have been experiencing a hollowing out of democracy. Politics has become nothing more than “governance,” the administration of the economy. In this sense, conspiracy theories are an expression of a diffuse unease. They point to the crisis of democracy. How many broken promises! How many betrayed hopes!

WOZ: But doesn’t democracy actually mean government or “sovereignty of the people”?

Donatella Di Cesare: And yet this sovereign people feels anything but sovereign. Democratic power seems to be slipping away from them. And this is not just a suspicion: democracy often seems completely illusory. Governments change, parties replace each other, but nothing really changes. What remains is the so-called deep state, the institutional power that is able to maintain and perpetuate itself thanks to castes, lobbies, banks, dynasties, and a few media corporations. That’s why I wouldn’t just call it a fantasy.

WOZ: What can be done to counter this dangerous feeling of political powerlessness?

Donatella Di Cesare: I don’t know. What is certainly problematic is the resentment that allows us to wallow in our own powerlessness. It is the new opium of the people. But it only confirms our own political powerlessness. Participation in the democratic process is the way forward. But first we need to think about conspiracy theories as an important sign. All I can say is that resentment prevails precisely where the principle of hope disappears.

WOZ: Can you elaborate on that?

Donatella Di Cesare: Conspiracy theories are neither a mental cramp nor merely a post-truth. Such stigmatization is misleading and ineffective. Recently, an anti-conspiracy movement has emerged that claims sole ownership of the truth and ridicules and delegitimizes theories that it considers deviant, irrational, and dangerous. Such overly simplistic anti-conspiracy thinking runs the risk of further hardening the lines between “official” and “hidden” truth. Basically, we are all conspiracy theorists—we have to admit that. Because when we hear about a new event, we all ask: What’s behind it?

 

WOZ: It’s actually an innocent question.

Donatella Di Cesare: Of course! And it’s an important question. The problem arises when questioning skepticism turns into dogmatic certainty.

WOZ: Let’s continue with the topic of politics: Right-wing politicians are currently benefiting most from the crisis of democracy you mentioned and the feelings of powerlessness that many people are experiencing. Is there a connection between conspiracy theories and the shift to the right?

Donatella Di Cesare: Absolutely. I would put it this way: we are currently experiencing a strong depoliticization. What does depoliticization mean? It means, for example, that we no longer participate in elections, which is a problem in many European countries.

WOZ: Why don’t people vote anymore?

Donatella Di Cesare: It’s just a symptom. The real depoliticization is the loss of the polis, that is, the loss of politics as a political community. Political ties are being lost. In this respect, it is a very dangerous phenomenon. One could even go so far as to say that depoliticization is already a symptom of a new authoritarian regime. We see this new form in Trumpism. We no longer believe in politics and democracy.

WOZ: What do we believe in instead?

Donatella Di Cesare: Well, I believe in politics and democracy. That’s why I try to point out the dangers, and I also want to regain the radical meaning of democracy.

WOZ: That sounds good. Are there any specific political movements you have in mind that are trying to do that?

Donatella Di Cesare: It’s not my job to point out the specific path. Besides, what does “specific” or ‘practical’ mean, and what does “theoretical” mean? I’m a philosopher, not a politician. My job is to think. Thinking is very dangerous, as we know, as Hannah Arendt said. And thinking is more important today than ever.

WOZ: In your book, you write that conspiracies are always constructs of meaning, explanations, simple narratives that name culprits and so on. But for a functioning democracy, we would need more complex meanings.

Donatella Di Cesare: I am talking about the “unreadability of the world.” The world seems to have fallen apart. The thread of the narrative has been broken. All that remains is an intricate web of intrigue that is difficult to unravel. Conspiracy theorists are, in a sense, nostalgic for legibility. They harbor the illusion that they can explain everything. The intrigue of which they see themselves as victims can thus be clarified. That is why they are so attracted to the political strategy of the new right, which points to a simple scapegoat and stokes fear.

WOZ: So you’re saying that the new right is ruling by playing on people’s fears?

Donatella Di Cesare: You could really call it a phobocracy. Power is exercised through phobos, through fear. This is what characterizes the new right’s government. They promise protection they can’t deliver. What’s more, they deliberately stir up fears, fuel hatred, and create enemies. Xenophobia and conspiracy theories are fundamental aspects of the same aversion to the “outside” and the foreign. What is Trump doing? What is Georgia Meloni doing? What is Viktor Orbán doing? They identify a perpetrator who can be considered guilty: Mexicans, transgender people, feminists, migrants. Conspiracy theories are a direct response to the complexity of this world. But instead of finding a solution, people constantly point to a scapegoat. This is a political strategy that is unfortunately gaining ground. We see it every day.

WOZ: Since you mentioned Georgia Meloni, how would you describe her government?

Donatella Di Cesare: For me, Meloni is different from Trump. She comes from the radical Italian right and is a post-fascist in every sense of the word. We have a post-fascist government. At first, this was traumatic for me—and not just for me. Especially in Italy, the country of Mussolini, where fascism was once born, the first post-fascist government in Europe is emerging after a hundred years. I would like to emphasize that first. But at the same time, I have to ask myself: Is Italy like Hungary? I was in Hungary recently and can answer: absolutely not.

 

WOZ: Why not?

Donatella Di Cesare: Because Italy has both a great left-wing tradition and a large left-wing movement. Unfortunately, however, this left wing is not adequately represented.

WOZ: What do you mean by that?

Donatella Di Cesare: I have often spoken of a “diffuse left” lately. I wouldn’t say that Italy is a country that has clearly shifted to the right. There are a lot of people in Italy who are left-wing. There are demonstrations every day. In many cities, there are protests, resistance, demonstrations. Countless numbers. So there is a lot of resistance in Italy. And of course Italy is a divided country, but it always has been. That’s also part of our history. It’s not easy to say whether the left will be represented in government in the future. Because it’s difficult to make good migration policy. We also have a big problem with poverty. We have a high rate of young people leaving the country. At the same time, we have a major demographic problem. So there are all these very complicated issues. And I fear that the wars and this plan to rearm Europe will have major negative consequences in Italy.

WOZ: You yourself have been a victim of the Meloni government (see “The courageous philosopher”). How do you see the situation of intellectuals in Italy today?

Donatella Di Cesare: In recent years, a number of intellectuals in Italy have been prosecuted. One trial after another took place, including mine, that of Luciano Canfora, a historian, that of the writer Roberto Saviano, and others. Since then, it has become more difficult to speak in public, I have to admit. I myself speak very often in public, on television, in public debates. And lately, I have often asked myself: Do I still feel as free as I did before?

WOZ: And what is your answer?

Donatella Di Cesare: I would say no. I no longer feel as free as I did before. And I probably won’t feel free again. I’ve also lost confidence. Nevertheless, I continue to speak out, as do other intellectuals. And almost every day, I say what people don’t want to hear, namely that we have a “post-fascist government.” But of course, I notice that freedom of expression in Italy has been greatly reduced. Everyone feels that way.

WOZ: You recently signed an open letter against the return of fascism. Can you say where you see differences, but also similarities, with historical fascism today?

Donatella Di Cesare: That’s an important question. Unlike other interpreters and political scientists, I am convinced that there is continuity between historical fascism and post-fascism. There are differences, but there are also similarities. I would like to mention just one of them, and that is the attempt to reduce the demos to the ethnos. For me, the main danger of Trump’s America or Meloni’s Italy or Orbán’s Hungary is that democracy is becoming ethnocracy. This means that ethnic boundaries are constantly being emphasized and defended. And that is what we saw in National Socialism and in Mussolini’s fascism. It suffices to mention the Nuremberg Laws of 1935 and the Italian racial laws of 1938. This interpretation of the demos as ethnos is the most important connection to historical fascism, and today it is decisive for migration policy and citizenship rights, for example. In Italy, for example, we have a reactionary citizenship law.

WOZ: Can you name another difference?

Donatella Di Cesare: There are many differences. Just look at the historical context, which was completely different. What seems decisive to me is the fact that Meloni’s post-fascism is spreading in a democratic context, which he nevertheless seeks to change.

WOZ: A widespread sentiment today, which is eagerly exploited by the right, is resentment. Why is it so difficult to harness powerful resentment for progressive politics?

Donatella Di Cesare: Of course, resentment could also be “used” for left-wing politics. We feel resentment, for example, when we believe we are victims of injustice. Resentment is a political emotion, and in this sense it is also justified. The difficulty for the left lies in “processing” individual resentment so that it can be elaborated and articulated for a common political project.

WOZ: The right wing processes such resentment into populist politics. In your book, you mention Ernesto Laclau, who, together with Chantal Mouffe, defined populism as an emancipatory force for the left. What is your view on populism?

Donatella Di Cesare: The question of populism is difficult. In Meloni’s view of Italy, there is a direct relationship between the head of government and the people. Why do we need the press? Why do we need intellectuals? It’s me and the people: that’s Meloni’s populist model. But I also agree with Ágnes Heller, the Hungarian philosopher who fought tirelessly against Orbán at the end of her life and analyzed the phenomenon of Orbánism. I would agree with her that Orbánism is not populism, but ethnic sovereignty. Orbán primarily stokes hatred against foreigners and anyone who is “different.”

WOZ: Is there also left-wing populism?

Donatella Di Cesare: To be populist, it is not enough to be close to the people, as is often claimed. We must not forget that populism has a history and manifests itself in different forms, especially in the Latin American context. It is not so much about an ideology as a political style that consists of mobilizing the masses against the elites. Populism can therefore also be left-wing, and above all it can offer an alternative to the prevailing crisis. French political scientist Jacques Rancière was right to use the word “populism” as a label for the crisis of legitimacy in politics. While left-wing populists appeal to the people, to the poorest sections of society, in order to revive their demands, Orbán uses nationalist populist rhetoric. And given the way he and the new right use populism, I prefer to speak of sovereignism or, as I said, ethnonationalism, because I think that is more precise.

_______________________________________________________ 

 

Leave a Comment